4.1 The Cappadocians
The main theological contribution of the Cappadocians – Basil the Great (330–379), Gregory of Nyssa (c. 335–c. 395), and Gregory of Nazianzus (329–389) – was the distinction between the one divine essence and the three hypostases that informed the theological decisions of the Second Ecumenical Council (381 CE). They argued that the distinction between the hypostasis of the Father, the Son, and the Holy Spirit does not divide God’s activity ad extra, which the three persons always perform jointly. The divine activity (energeia) proceeds from God’s entire essence (ousia) or nature (physis), although every hypostasis fulfils a specific function in the divine acts of self-manifestation. On the level of the divine economy (oikonomia),
every operation (energeia) which extends from God to the Creation, and is named according to our variable conceptions of it, has its origin from (ek) the Father, and proceeds through (dia) the Son, and is perfected in (en) the Holy Spirit. (Gregory of Nyssa, On ‘Not Three Gods’; 1979a: 334)
On the intra-trinitarian level (theologia), the Father is the cause or origin of the second and the third hypostasis: the Son is begotten (gennētos) of the unbegotten (agennētos) Father, and the Holy Spirits proceeds (ekporeuetai) from the Father. This is not to say that the Son is ontologically subordinated to the Father, or the Holy Spirit to the Son. Unlike Eunomius, the Cappadocians teach that the three hypostases have one common divine essence (ousia), nature (physis), and deity (theotēs). All three hypostases of the Trinity are co-eternal and co-equal, but have their specific identifying characteristics (gnōristikai idiotētes).
The Cappadocians strongly emphasize the simplicity and indivisibility of the divine essence (Gregory of Nyssa, Against Eunomius II.12.475). Accordingly, some scholars argue that the distinction between the divine essence and energy in Gregory of Nyssa should not be interpreted in terms of an ontological difference, for this would introduce composition into God (Renczes 2003: 115–116). Moreover, according to the Cappadocians’ notion of deification (theōsis), believers become ‘God by grace’, by participating in the uncreated divine energies. Reflecting on the different meanings of the phrase ‘in (en) the Holy Spirit’, Basil of Caesarea writes about the diachronic indwelling of the energeia of the Holy Spirit in the believer. While the grace of the Spirit is continuously present, it must be synergistically actualized by the recipient to be effective and bring spiritual fruits, such as prophecies and healings. It follows from this that the divine energeia bestowed by the Holy Spirit can be present in the believer both potentially and in an actualized state (On the Holy Spirit 61; 1895b: 38–39; see Bradshaw 2004: 173).
Apart from the simplicity and indivisibility of the divine essence, the Cappadocians also maintain its inaccessibility. They explain that humans can only know God’s attributes such as his greatness, his power, his wisdom, or his goodness, which become manifest through the energies, and not God’s essence itself. Basil of Caesarea writes that God’s ‘operations [energeiai] come down to us, but His essence remains beyond our reach’ (Letter 234; 1895a: 274), and Gregory of Nazianzus confirms that ‘no one has yet discovered or ever shall discover what God is in his nature (physis) and essence (ousia)’ (Oratio 28.17; Gregory of Nazianzus 2002: 49).
Some commentators see here a problematic Neoplatonic influence that precipitated a certain disjunction between oikonomia – God’s enactment of the plan of salvation in creation – and theologia – the divine life ‘in itself’ (Renczes 2003: 117; LaCugna 1991: 69–73). Refuting Arian and Eunomian subordinationism, the Cappadocians insisted on the consubstantiality and coequality of the three hypostases. Yet, as a result, these commentators argue, the intra-trinitarian relationships and the inaccessibility of the divine essence took precedence over the divine economy – a development that also gradually impacted the liturgical texts of the church. In earlier doxological formulas, praise was given to the Father through the Son, in the Holy Spirit, indicating their specific function in the divine economy – as mentioned above. Later doxologies, however, emphasized the equality of the three persons and thus directed praise to the Father and the Son and the Holy Spirit (LaCugna 1991: 111–135; Jungmann 1989: 172–190).
4.2 Maximus the Confessor
Maximus the Confessor’s (c. 580–662) understanding of the essence-energy distinction builds mainly upon Dionysius the Areopagite and the Cappadocians. In Maximus’ writings, the concept of energeia is of central importance with respect to the doctrine of God, Christology, cosmology, and anthropology. Energy does not have a hypostatic character but ontologically belongs to the essence or nature, which is common in beings that belong to the same genus (Amb. 23, PG 91:1261A; Maximus the Confessor 2014: 9 [vol. 2]). Regarding the doctrine of the Trinity, this means that there is one common essence and one common energy but three hypostases.
Maximus was a leading figure in the theological struggle against imperially imposed monoenergism and monotheletism, which taught that Christ had only one energy and one will (Blowers 2016: 42–54). He argued that, following the doctrine of the two natures of Christ established at the Fourth Ecumenical Council in Chalcedon (451 CE), there must also be two energies and two wills in Christ. Maximus writes that
[…] because His divine energy was humanized through its ineffable union with the natural energy of the flesh, He completed the plan of salvation on our behalf […but] the union, by excluding division, does not impair the distinction. (Amb. 5, PG 91:1056B–D; Maximus the Confessor 2014: 51 [vol. 1])
Both God and human beings, the uncreated and the created, possess a ‘natural energy’ through which the nature/essence expresses and manifests itself.
According to Maximus, Jesus Christ is the ‘beginning’, ‘middle’, and ‘end’ of all created beings. This triad corresponds to several other triads that he uses to set out his Christian metaphysics. As beginning, God is the ‘creator’, as middle the ‘provider’, and as end the ‘goal’ of creation (Chapters on Knowledge I.10; Maximus the Confessor 1985: 130). Maximus refers to the same three aspects of divine activity (energeia) when he differentiates between ‘being’, ‘well-being’, and ‘eternal-being’. It is the one God who endows us with being, guides and directs our movement to him (well-being), and accomplishes our deification by grace (eternal-being) (Amb. 7, PG 91:1076B–C; 2014: 89–91 [vol. 1]; Amb. 10, PG 91:1116B; 2014: 167–169 [vol. 1]). While God as Creator is always active (kat’ energeian), creatures must realize the potency (dynamis) that was given to them by God. That is to say, the potency (dynamis) that inheres in the essence (ousia) of created beings must be turned into actuality (energeia; Amb. 7, PG 91:1081A; Maximus the Confessor 2014: 99–101 [vol. 1]; Chapters on Knowledge 1.3; Maximus the Confessor 1985: 129). The divine energies actualize the human nature, which is always already directed to the divine telos. God is not only the creator and preserver of creatures, but also effects their movement towards God, and their fulfilment.
The distribution and reception of the divine energies takes place analogically and synergistically. Created beings are many and therefore also different, and God’s infinite energies are present in each of them, according to the divinely-instituted ‘natural principles’ (logoi) that determine their essences. All logoi of beings are rooted in the one Logos, the Word of God. God is wholly present in each of his energies, without losing his indivisible simplicity (Larchet 2010: 396). Furthermore, God’s energy is present in creatures in proportion to the receptive capacity of the human recipient; in proportion to a person’s measure of faith and disposition of the soul (Amb. 22, PG 91:1256D–1257C; Maximus the Confessor 2014: 449–451 [vol. 1]; Ad Thal. 29 CCSG 7:211; Maximus the Confessor 2018: 196–197). Synergism between God and human beings takes place in the middle phase of Maximus’ metaphysical triads, where ‘being’ is qualified as ‘well-being’. The reception of the divine energies requires an active response on the part of the human recipient and enables the believer to (re)direct his ‘faculty of judging’ (gnomē) by acquiring a particular habitus (hexis). In this dialogical encounter with God, a person’s ‘mode of existence’ comes to realize the underlying ‘natural principle’ (logos physeōs), which is fixed and inalterable.
Deification, the becoming of God by grace by participating in the uncreated divine energies, cannot be realized individually, but only ecclesially and eucharistically (Loudovikos 2010: 195–210). Communion with God, and the dynamic actualization of ‘being’ as ‘well-being’ and ‘eternal being’, is concomitant with the realization of interpersonal communion. In the Eucharist, all people, despite their cultural, linguistic, and educational differences, and despite their different ages, appearances, characters, opinions and skills, are gathered and unified in the one Logos, Jesus Christ, yet without loss of integrity and without confusion (Mystagogy I: Maximus the Confessor 1985: 186–188). ‘Being’ for Maximus is thus realized as ‘becoming-in-communion’. The individual believer’s love of God and her movement towards God are integrated into the Eucharistic community. Only in the divine Eucharist is ontologically real incorporation of the Christian into the body of Christ possible.
4.3 Gregory Palamas
Particularly in the West, the essence-energy distinction is primarily associated with the late Byzantine theologian Gregory Palamas (1296–1357). While the basic features of this doctrine clearly predate Palamas by centuries, scholars still investigate how Palamas’ interpretation of this doctrine refers to that of earlier Byzantine and patristic authors. There are two distinct but interrelated issues: first, there is the historical question about the degree of continuity and discontinuity between Palamas and his predecessors; and second, there is the theological question of how to evaluate Palamas’ interpretation or development of this doctrine.
In the course of the controversy that was stirred up at the time of Palamas, theological reflection about the essence-energy distinction intensified, resulting in a deeper understanding of the underlying key issues. Like earlier Greek patristic authors, Palamas resorted to this doctrine to conceive of the divine presence, the real presence of God in creation, without impairing the divine transcendence. The debates mainly revolved around the question of the precise ontological status of the divine energy and its relationship to the divine essence. Moreover, the question of the theologically appropriate use of pre-Christian philosophical concepts and ideas, the question of the relationship between philosophical and theological knowledge, gained renewed attention.
The Palamite controversy originated in the context of hesychast spirituality on Mount Athos. The historical roots of hesychasm, derived from the Greek word hesychia, ‘stillness’, can be traced back to the emerging monasticism, particularly the anchorite way of life in fourth-century Egypt and Palestine. Building on the spiritual experience of Evagrius Ponticus, Macarius the Great, Diadochus of Photice, John Climacus, and many other ascetics, hesychasm centres on the repetition of the Jesus Prayer: ‘Lord Jesus Christ, Son of God, have mercy upon me a sinner’. The highest goal of the hesychast is to reach a state of unceasing prayer, purification from sin, transformation of the passions, and union with God (Stăniloae 2003). Palamas and his contemporaries were mainly concerned about the correct theological interpretation of the visions of divine light experienced by the monks, which they identified with the light that shone forth from Christ’s countenance at the transfiguration on Mount Tabor (see section 3.3). The doctrine of the divine energies was used as a conceptual tool to theologically interpret these mystical visions of God.
According to most contemporary scholars, Gregory Palamas was not a radical innovator who brought about a ground-breaking paradigm change in Byzantine theology. Rather, his work is seen as a creative synthesis of the many different but overlapping concepts and ideas used in connection with the doctrine of the divine energies in earlier centuries (Bradshaw 2004: 241; Loudovikos 2013: 124; Russell 2019: 210; Tollefsen 2012: 185). The debates into which he was drawn by his opponents, most notably Barlaam, Akindynos, and Gregoras, advanced theological reflection on the doctrine of the divine energies. What is to some extent new in Palamas’ work, according to Norman Russell, is the emphasis on the personal experience of divine grace in contemplative prayer realizable in this life. Palamas even goes so far as to say that the saints who have achieved deification by grace become ‘wholly one with God’ (homotheoi) – an expression the church fathers used christologically to talk about the deified body of Christ (On Divine Energies 36; Palamas 1966b: 121–122 [vol. 2]; Russell 2006: 357, 370 note 52). Palamas’ understanding of deification through participation in the uncreated divine energies remains fully embedded in the liturgical, sacramental, and hierarchical life of the church.
Palamas explains that the saints participate in the ‘whole of God’, not in his essence but in his energies, for otherwise they would become gods by nature (Triads III.3.8; Palamas 1973: 709–711 [vol. 2]). He points out that the divine essence and energy are not identical and (following Dionysius the Areopagite) a distinction must be drawn between the imparticipable (amethekton) which is the divine essence, the participable (methekton) which is the divine energy, and that which participates (metechon), which is created beings. The divine energies mediate between the one uncreated divine essence and the plurality of created participating beings (Triads III.2.25; Palamas 1973: 686–688 [vol. 2]). What remains to be defined is the precise relationship between the imparticipable (the divine essence) and the participable (the divine energy).
In one of his letters, addressed to Akindynos, Palamas distinguishes between the ‘superior essence’ (huperkeimenē ousia) and the ‘lower divinity’ (theotēs hupheimenē), and uses the latter expression to refer to the divine energy and the gift of deification (Third Letter to Akindynos, section 15; Palamas 1966c: 306–307 [vol. 1]). His opponents viewed this theologically ambiguous passage as an epitome of his ditheism (150 Chapters, section 147; Palamas 1988: 252–253) and interpreted it in terms of a (Neoplatonic) hierarchy of divine beings, consisting of ‘lower’ and ‘higher’ deities. (There are historical, exegetical, and editorial questions about this passage, which has a slightly different meaning in different versions of the letter.) In this letter, Palamas in fact reacts to a lost treatise by Barlaam, who accused him of dividing God into a ‘higher’ and a ‘lower’ deity. In his response, Palamas excludes ditheism and a crude ontological subordinationism (Pino 2022: 138–143). Throughout his entire work, he insists that the essence-energy distinction does not undermine the simplicity of God (Plested 2019).
The main theological and philosophical question is how Palamas conceived of the distinction between essence and energy (Bradshaw 2023: 81–117). There are contemporary scholars who identify a real distinction (distinctio realis) between the divine essence and energy in Palamas’ writings. Some see this position as theologically convincing and inevitable (Meyendorff 1983: 186–188), others as problematic because it impairs the divine simplicity (Demetracopoulos 2011: 272–280). A third group of commentators argues that the expression ‘real distinction’ does not capture Palamas’ main theological intention (Tollefsen 2012: 198), and either regard the essence-energy distinction as a notional distinction (kat’ epinoian) (Loudovikos 2013) or as a conceptual distinction with an ontological foundation (distinctio rationis cum fundamento in re; Lévy 2012; Russell 2019: 183). Yet others see a certain similarity between the essence-energy distinction and Duns Scotus’ formal distinction (Bradshaw 2023: 116; Milbank 2013; Spencer 2017: 130, note 30). The comparison between Palamas and Scotus is not new but goes back to Gennadios Scholarios (1400–c. 1473; Kapriev 2018).
Some of the passages in Palamas’ work that emphasize the difference between essence and energy precisely exclude an ontological subordination of the energies. For instance, Palamas argues that if the Father is greater than the Son (cf. John 14:28), despite the fact that the Son possesses his own hypostasis (authypostatos) and is of one essence with the Father (homoousios), all the more will the essence be superior to the energy (On the Divine Energies, section 19; Palamas 1966b: 111 [vol. 2]). In other words, Palamas sees a certain similarity between the way the Father is the cause (aitia) of the Son, and the way the essence is the cause of the energy. The notion of the monarchy of the Father in Greek patristic trinitarian thought is complex and has very little to do with what is normally understood by cause and causality (Loudovikos 2011: 688–696; see also Bulgakov 2004: 134–137). What is clear is that Palamas seeks to find a model of ‘difference-in-unity’ that avoids a crude ontological subordinationism.
According to Palamas, the most fundamental difference between the Father-Son relationship and the essence-energy distinction is that the energy does not exist as an independent reality (kat’ heauto), i.e. it is not self-subsistent. Unlike the Son, the energy does not possess a hypostasis of its own (authypostatos). Nor is it anhypostatic (anhypostatos), for this term denotes non-being or illusionary being, or things of fleeting existence such as uttered words and the ever-changing atmospheric conditions. Palamas calls the uncreated divine light enhypostatic (enhypostatos) to underline first its reality, permanence, and stability, and second its ontological dependence on a hypostasis in which it has its existence (Triads III.1.9; 17–18; Palamas 1973: 572–573 [vol. 2]). In the eighth century, John of Damascus had used the term enhypostatos to conceive of the assumption of Christ’s human nature by the hypostasis of God the Word (The Fount of Knowledge, section 44; John of Damascus 1999: 68–69). In Palamas, the divine energy is enhypostatic in the sense that it pertains to the divine nature of Christ, and to the divinity or essence of the entire Trinity (Triads III 1.12, 19; Palamas 1973: 580–582, 592–594 [vol. 2]). In his later writings, however, the meaning of the term enhypostatos changes and comes to denote self-subsistence (authypostatos). Accordingly, it is no longer used to characterize the divine energies (Pino 2022: 152–155).
Palamas insists that, although God’s essence surpasses the energy ‘to the extent that the subject of an action (to energoun) surpasses its object (to energoumenos)’, God is nonetheless ‘entirely manifest in every energy’ (Triads III 2, 9–10; Palamas 1973: 658–662 [vol. 2]; 150 Chapters, section 75). As he writes:
But since God is entirely (holon) present in each of the divine energies, we name Him from each of them, although it is clear that he transcends all of them. For, given the multitude of divine energies, how could God subsist entirely (holos) in each without any division at all; and how could each provide Him with a name and manifest Him entirely (holos), thanks to indivisible and supernatural simplicity, if He did not transcend all these energies? (Triads III.2.7; Palamas 1973: 656–657 [vol. 2])
In this quotation, Palamas does not simply distinguish between a part of God that is inaccessible and imparticipable and a part that is accessible and participable. Rather, in the above passage, the theological rationale underlying the essence-energy distinction could be articulated as follows: the transcendent essence is envisaged as the condition of possibility of God’s unreserved self-giving in his energies. God does not remain hidden in the sense that his self-giving is somehow restricted. His indivisible and supernatural simplicity is the precondition that God can manifest himself without reserve while remaining transcendent.
Furthermore, in Palamas, the Aristotelian differentiation between dynamis (potentiality, capacity) and energeia (actuality, activity) takes on a new meaning. In his writings, dynamis and energeia are viewed as synonyms and denote the power of God that is eternally and unceasingly active, but not always manifest in the creaturely sphere (On Divine Energies 23; Palamas 1966b: 113–114 [vol. 2]). In other words, God’s energeia/dynamis, his inherent and essential power, is distinguished from his activities (energeiai) ad extra, through which this power becomes manifest in time (Pino 2022: 94–99). The term energeia thus has a double meaning. But Palamas insists that even energeia understood as essential power of God is not an unrealized potentiality prior to God’s use of this power, since God is active from all eternity (150 Chapters section 140; Palamas 1988: 244–245). Consequently, when Palamas talks about the beginning or end of the divine energies, he refers to the manifestation of these energies in space and time, and not to the energies as a pre-eternal power (Antirrhetics 6.20.75; Palamas 1966a: 442–443 [vol. 3]; Pino 2022: 91–94). Palamas calls the internal energies also natural or inherent attributes of God (prosonta), or divine predicates, properties, or idioms (Pino 2022: 65–67).